Trump Immunity Case: Will SCOTUS Decide It Based on the Constitution’s Text or Make Something Up?

If the Trump immunity case is decided using textualist and originalist interpretive methods,[1]See here and here. the answer is straightforward. Nothing in the text of the Constitution or federal statutory law references presidential immunity from criminal prosecution for conduct while in office. Rather, the constitutional language closest on point indicates that there is no such immunity.

The Speech or Debate Clause (Article I, section 6, clause 1) shows that the framers of the Constitution knew how to confer immunity if they wanted to, and they did so explicitly. It provides that senators and representatives–

“shall in all Cases, except Treason, Felony and Breach of the Peace, be privileged from Arrest during their Attendance at the Session of their respective Houses, and in going to and returning from the same; and for any Speech or Debate in either House, they shall not be questioned in any other Place.”

No comparable provision applies to the president. Even more to the point, Article I, section 3, clause 7 of the Constitution provides:

“Judgment in Cases of Impeachment shall not extend further than to removal from Office, and disqualification to hold and enjoy any Office of honor, Trust or Profit under the United States: but the Party convicted shall nevertheless be liable and subject to Indictment, Trial, Judgment and Punishment, according to Law.” (Emphasis supplied)

As even Trump’s lawyers concede, this provision affirms that former presidents can be subject to criminal prosecution.[2]His lawyers make the ludicrous argument, which nobody seems to buy, that prosecution can occur only if an official has first been impeached and convicted. This provision also undercuts the notion that there is a difference for purposes of criminal prosecution between a president’s official and private acts. The post-impeachment criminal liability it refers to draws no such distinction but applies to all impeachable acts.    

Aside from the absence of textual support, other factors weigh against presidential criminal immunity. Historical context makes it wholly implausible that the framers had the slightest interest in exempting presidents from the criminal law. Having recently won freedom from the British crown, they firmly rejected the concept of the president as akin to a king who would be above the law.

Thankfully, we don’t have much tradition of potential criminal conduct by past presidents. What little there is indicates an understanding that presidents are subject to prosecution for their conduct in office. Former President Nixon accepted a pardon for any criminal liability relating to Watergate. President Clinton negotiated a plea deal to avoid prosecution arising from the Ken Starr investigation. Notably, President Trump’s defense attorneys in his second impeachment trial maintained that the proper remedy for any misconduct on his part was criminal prosecution—a position endorsed by many senators who voted for his acquittal.[3]The opinion by the D.C. Circuit elaborates on these points.

In a 1982 decision, Nixon v. Fitzgerald, the Supreme Court held that presidents have absolute immunity from civil liability for conduct within the “outer perimeter” of their official duties. However, this 5-4 decision from the pre-textualist era is itself dubious and likewise lacks any foundation in the words of the Constitution. In any event, as the Nixon opinion recognized, different considerations apply to civil versus criminal immunity.

Consistent with the foregoing, lower court trial and appellate judges unanimously rejected Trump’s immunity claims. Nevertheless, the Supreme Court decided to take up the case. Based on the oral argument, it appears likely that the Court’s conservative justices will once again depart from the textualism/originalism they claim to favor and find at least some sort of presidential criminal immunity.

The oral argument featured a hypothetical-laden free for all that focused heavily on the policy pros and cons of presidential criminal immunity but gave scant attention to the Constitution’s text and history. Remarkably, the argument also largely avoided the facts of the Trump case.

Even the policy debate was somewhat bizarre. Conservative justices emphasized how the prospect of criminal liability could inhibit presidents in the performance of their functions. On the flip side, however, deterring unlawful behavior is of course a primary purpose of the criminal law. Some justices also expressed great concern over the potential danger that prosecutors could act in bad faith to go after a former president, but they ignored the massive evidence of Trump’s actual bad faith that underlies the criminal charges against him.

The justices also struggled to find a coherent, workable dividing line between official acts by a president that might be subject to immunity and acts outside the president’s official responsibilities, which most if not all justices seemed to agree would not be immunized. But isn’t criminal malfeasance in office by a president just as bad, indeed probably worse, than non-official criminal misconduct?

As noted at the outset, this is an excellent example of a case in which textualism and originalism provide a clear, legally sound resolution: There is no specific basis in the Constitution’s text and history to exempt presidents from the criminal laws that apply to all other citizens. Unfortunately, the Court may eschew this approach in favor of a muddled decision unmoored from the Constitution’s language.

Textualists and originalists accuse those who favor more free wheeling interpretive methods of making stuff up.” They are particularly critical of announcing constitutional rights or protections that are nowhere mentioned in its text. Yet, the conservative justices seem poised to do just that in this case. If they do, it would have been better for the Court to stay out of the case altogether.     

 

     

Footnotes

Footnotes
1 See here and here.
2 His lawyers make the ludicrous argument, which nobody seems to buy, that prosecution can occur only if an official has first been impeached and convicted.
3 The opinion by the D.C. Circuit elaborates on these points.

A “Crisis” in Con Law Teaching?

The New York Times recently published a remarkable op-ed by Jesse Wegman captioned “The Crisis in Teaching Constitutional Law.” Wegman observes that Con Law professors traditionally operate under the premise that the Supreme Court is “a legitimate institution of governance,” the justices “care about getting the law right,” and they are more concerned with “upholding fundamental democratic principles” than “imposing a partisan agenda.” He then asserts that this premise “no longer holds today.”

Wegman claims that the Court, “under the pretense of practicing so-called originalism,” issues decisions that “virtually always [align] with the policy priorities of the modern Republican Party.” This, in turn, “has made it impossible for many professors to teach in the familiar way.”

He quotes one distraught Con Law professor who describes his job as “teaching students what the law isn’t.” Another was reduced to tears and felt “depleted.” She couldn’t see how “any of this makes sense” or why she should “respect it.” A third quit, saying that he “couldn’t stand up in front of the class and pretend the students should take the Court’s decisions seriously in terms of legal analysis.”

The arrogance of these professors (and Wegman) is striking. For them, the certainty that they are right and the Court is wrong apparently leaves no room for good faith debate or honest difference of opinion over the merits of its decisions and interpretive methods. Rather, the Court has simply ceased to be a legitimate institution in their eyes and its decisions no longer constitute valid sources of law.

A small group of disgruntled law professors does not make for a “crisis.”[1]Wegman interviewed fewer than 20 professors. He admits most were politically liberal, as are most Con Law professors in the country. However, their sentiments may be shared by many others in the legal academy and among political and media influencers. The dean of one prominent law school shamefully endorsed the description of Supreme Court justices as “partisan hacks.” Recent years have witnessed relentless attacks from many corners on the legitimacy of the Court and the integrity of the justices. The Court and its members are portrayed as thoroughly politicized, intellectually dishonest, unethical, and wholly at odds with American public opinion.

These caricatures are as baseless as they are extreme. Objective data refute the notion that the Court operates like a conservative monolith producing radical decisions that are out of touch with the American public:

    • The Court’s decisions rarely break down into 6-3 splits between the conservative and liberal justices. There is far more consensus than one would think from media reports. (See here)
    • When there are split decisions, the six conservative justices diverge considerably more among themselves than do the three liberals. The liberals vote far more frequently as a block, particularly in politically charged cases. (See here)
    • Contrary to media assertions, the current Court is less likely than its predecessors to overrule precedents. (See here)
    • More often than not, the Court’s decisions in controversial cases align with public opinion. In fact, the Court is much more in tune with the American public as a whole than are the law professors. (See here and here)
    • No serious ethics violations or corrupt acts have been identified regarding any justice. Tireless media efforts to find them uncovered only some ambiguities and errors regarding financial disclosure reporting. (See here and here)

The accusation that the justices are mere politicians in robes is equally unfounded. Tellingly, former Justice Stephen Breyer, a leading liberal critic of the Court (and a less partisan one), firmly rejects the notion that the justices are political actors. He does not question their integrity or good faith, only their jurisprudence.

What really accounts for the almost visceral contempt the law professors (and others like Wegman) apparently hold for the Court is a change in its dominant judicial philosophy that, while at odds with their own, is perfectly legitimate and even salutary. 

Many of today’s law professors came of age in the heady era starting with the Warren Court and lasting for decades when judge-made law served as an important and reliable instrument for advancing liberal political causes. One law professor told Wegman that the professors who taught his generation “were all Warren court people” who “valorized” it. They regarded its members as “heroes who would save us all.”

The free-wheeling decisions by the justices who dominated the Court in those years consistently aligned with values the law professors share. However, many of those decisions were less than meticulous (to be charitable) when it came to their legal reasoning. They often glossed over statutory and constitutional language. For example, a 1965 decision found a constitutional right to privacy based on “penumbras, formed by emanations from” the Constitution. Another decision resorted to the text of a law in order to resolve ambiguities in its legislative history.

Spearheaded by former Justice Antonin Scalia, the Court in more recent years has shifted its focus to what the relevant law actually says and means. Far from being “pretenses,” textualism and originalism are conceptually sound interpretive methods and well within the mainstream of legal thought.[2]See here and here. In fact, they have been endorsed in concept by liberal Justices Kagan and Jackson. Of course, it’s fair to critique when and how the Court applies these methods in specific cases. Indeed, the liberal justices frequently accuse their conservative colleagues of invoking them selectively. But properly used, textualism and originalism can provide a much-needed, more objective framework for deciding cases.

No doubt a major gap does exist between what many recent Supreme Court decisions say the law is and what overwhelmingly liberal law professors would prefer the law to be. However, the blame for any resulting teaching “crisis” lies with the law professors, not the Court.

Like anyone else, law professors are certainly free to disagree with the Court’s ideological turn and its embrace of textualism and originalism. However, it is irresponsible and unprofessional to disparage the Court to law students as a rogue institution whose decisions should not be respected. This is also a grave disservice to the students, most of whom will practice in the real world.

Professors who can no longer bring themselves to teach Con Law in a traditional, straightforward way should follow the lead of one of Wegman’s interviewees and find another line of work.

 

 

 

 

 

 

Footnotes

Footnotes
1 Wegman interviewed fewer than 20 professors. He admits most were politically liberal, as are most Con Law professors in the country.
2 See here and here.

Justice Breyer Versus Textualism and Originalism

Retired Supreme Court Justice Stephen Breyer is making the media rounds[1]See here, here, and here. to discuss his new book entitled “Reading the Constitution: Why I Chose Pragmatism, Not Textualism.” As the title suggests, he rejects the Supreme Court’s use of “textualism” as a method of interpreting the law. He also criticizes its use of “originalism” to interpret the Constitution.

Notably, Justice Breyer wants no part of the vitriolic attacks on the Court that have become commonplace on the left—denying its “legitimacy” and dismissing the Justices as ethically challenged “political hacks.” He does not accuse them of acting in bad faith or from partisan political motives. Rather, his criticisms center on differences in jurisprudential philosophy.

The civil tone and substantive nature of Justice Breyer’s critiques are a welcome relief from the unhinged rants aimed at the Court these days. But is he right?

Certainly, the Court’s use of textualism and originalism is subject to legitimate criticism. It has rightly been accused of inconsistency and selectivity in invoking them.[2]For example, the Court’s recent unanimous decision in Trump v. Anderson contradicts both the text and original meaning of section 3 of the Fourteenth Amendment. Conservative judges differ among themselves on what these concepts entail[3] See, e.g., here. and how they apply in specific cases.[4]In Bostock v. Clayton County, conservative Justices disagreed fiercely with each other over the right textualist interpretation of a statute. And as Justice Breyer notes, the Court’s use of history to discern the original meaning of constitutional provisions can be especially dicey.[5]The Court’s decision in New York State Rifle & Pistol Assn v. Bruen is a much-criticized example.

Finally, these interpretive methodologies are hardly silver bullets. Few cases reaching the Supreme Court involve issues of statutory or constitutional interpretation that can easily be decided based on unambiguous text or readily apparent original meaning. (Of course, this limitation applies to any interpretive method; cases with obvious answers rarely come before the Court.)

Nevertheless, both textualism and originalism are conceptually sound, indeed compelling. Applied consistently and where feasible, both can instill much needed discipline into the business of judging.

Textualism focuses on the actual words of written law (statutory or constitutional). It does so for one obvious and fundamental reason: The language of a statute or constitutional provision embodies what the law is; as such, it provides the best evidence–indeed the only authoritative evidence—of what the law means. It follows that any credible interpretation of the law’s meaning must be anchored in its text.

Contrary to Justice Breyer’s caricature, textualism is far from a simplistic, wooden exercise that fetishizes grammar and punctuation. Interpreting statutory text is a complex, sophisticated task that involves a host of well-established and mainly logical, common-sense principles and presumptions (so-called “canons”).[6]See here for a description of some of prominent canons. And while textualism centers on the language of the law, it is not confined to the four corners of the document. Other sources may be considered–e.g., context, relationship to other laws, even legislative history–if they are relevant and useful to discerning the meaning of the language.[7]While some textualists (including former Justice Scalia) distain legislative history, most see a role for it in helping to resolve ambiguities in the text. Non-textualists have been known to do the … Continue reading

Originalism as a means of interpreting the Constitution is closely related to textualism. It holds that the Constitution should be construed in accordance with the meaning of its language as understood at the time it was adopted. The premise is that the meaning of the Constitution cannot change on its own without a corresponding change in its text via formal amendment.[8]See here for background.

Justice Breyer favors an alternative jurisprudential approach that views the Constitution as a “living” document whose meaning can “evolve” without benefit of formal amendment to better reflect contemporary mores and values. After all, he observes, “half the country wasn’t represented in the political process that led to the document.”

It’s true that the United States and its body politic look much different now from when the Constitution was adopted. Some constitutional provisions may seem anachronistic and undemocratic—e.g., the electoral college, the composition of the Senate. However, they obviously can’t unilaterally evolve to mean something other than what they say.

Even as to less specific provisions, the notion that the Constitution’s meaning can evolve to better reflect contemporary values and mores doesn’t guarantee change for the better; change can also be regressive. Many of today’s political influencers, particularly in academia and elsewhere on the left, increasingly disfavor or at best downplay traditional concepts of freedom of speech, due process, and equal protection. Living constitutionalist judges could conceivably retrench these fundamental rights on the basis that society values them less now than it once did.

In the final analysis, originalism versus living constitutionalism and textualism versus other means of statutory interpretation[9] See here. may come down to how one sees the role of judges.

Justice Breyer views judges as problem-solvers who should interpret a law (statutory or constitutional) by “consider[ing] a problem from every angle,” as he put it in one interview. This includes assessing the law’s purposes and consequences, and whether it makes sense in relation to contemporary circumstances and values. By contrast, textualists and originalists see the judicial role as more modest–seeking to ascertain and defer to the choices the elected representatives of the people made as set forth in the enacted law. They favor relying on democratic processes to decide by formal amendment when and how the law needs to change.

With due respect to Justice Breyer, I’d submit that textualism and originalism, with all their limitations, are preferable to the alternatives.

 

 

 

Footnotes

Footnotes
1 See here, here, and here.
2 For example, the Court’s recent unanimous decision in Trump v. Anderson contradicts both the text and original meaning of section 3 of the Fourteenth Amendment.
3 See, e.g., here.
4 In Bostock v. Clayton County, conservative Justices disagreed fiercely with each other over the right textualist interpretation of a statute.
5 The Court’s decision in New York State Rifle & Pistol Assn v. Bruen is a much-criticized example.
6 See here for a description of some of prominent canons.
7 While some textualists (including former Justice Scalia) distain legislative history, most see a role for it in helping to resolve ambiguities in the text. Non-textualists have been known to do the opposite—resorting to statutory text when necessary to resolve ambiguities in the legislative history. See Citizens to Preserve Overton Park v. Volpe, 401 U.S. 402, 412, fn. 29 (1971).
8 See here for background.
9 See here.

Trump v. Anderson: Right Result, Wrong Reasons

Section 3 of the Fourteenth Amendment disqualifies from a wide range of State and federal offices individuals who took an oath to support the Constitution and then “engaged in insurrection or rebellion” against the United States or gave “aid or comfort” to its “enemies.” In Trump v. Anderson, the Supreme Court unanimously reversed a Colorado Supreme Court decision holding that section 3 disqualified Donald Trump from running for president.

What to make of this decision?

Putting aside for the moment its legal merits, there’s much to be said for the outcome. As the opinion observes, allowing individual States to strike federal candidates (particularly presidential candidates) from the ballot under section 3, probably applying different legal and evidentiary standards to determine whether they “engaged in insurrection,” could produce a “patchwork” of results creating chaos in elections. Invoking section 3 to challenge candidates once elected and even serving in office would be still more chaotic.

Disqualifying the odds-on favorite to be the presidential nominee of a major party also would be a tremendous shock to the political system. But the consequences of injecting section 3 into our ever more toxic politics go beyond Trump and the 2024 election. Attempted disqualification would likely become a popular new form of lawfare in many future elections, especially given the “sweeping” scope its leading advocates, such as law professors William Baude and Michael Stokes Paulsen, attribute to the term “insurrection.”

All this would be based on resurrecting an obscure constitutional provision enacted with a specific purpose in mind—barring from office Confederates who waged war against the United States—that was accomplished over a century ago and extending it far beyond its original context. The potential consequences of affirming the Colorado decision were so extreme that even many Trump opponents had qualms about it and hardly anyone expected the Supreme Court to uphold it.

As a practical matter, the Supreme Court’s decision appears to return section 3 to the mists of history with regard to the presidency and every other federal office.[1] The Court specifically held that States could enforce section 3 against their own officials. All nine Justices agreed that States could not enforce section 3 against federal candidates and officials. To the consternation of four Justices, the other five went further and seemingly concluded that additional congressional legislation would be needed to enable even federal enforcement against federal candidates and officials. Given Congress’s dysfunction and gridlock, it’s extremely unlikely that Congress could enact such legislation.  

While the practical considerations underlying the Court’s decision may be compelling, its legal reasoning is not. The unanimous holding that States cannot enforce section 3 against federal candidates seems wrong on many levels. By its terms, section 3 clearly appears to be self-executing in the sense that disqualification attaches automatically to those it describes:

No [such] person shall be a Senator or Representative in Congress, or elector of President and Vice-President, or hold any office, civil or military, under the United States, or under any State.” (Emphasis added)

The final sentence of section 3 reinforces this conclusion by authorizing Congress to “remove” the “disability” that it imposes.  

Section 5 of the Fourteenth Amendment empowers Congress to enforce its many provisions by appropriate legislation. However, it does not explicitly or implicitly preclude State enforcement as well. On the contrary, with exceptions not relevant here States  share both the power and the obligation to enforce the Constitution. Article VI, clause 3 requires State officials to take the same oath as their federal counterparts to support the Constitution.

In fact, States regularly enforce the provisions of the Fourteenth Amendment and many other constitutional provisions including those governing eligibility for federal elective office such as age, citizenship, and residence requirements. Enforcing section 3 obviously differs in complexity but not in kind.

The Court reasons that the Fourteenth Amendment was enacted to enhance federal power at the expense of State authority and, therefore, it would be “incongruous” to read it “as granting to the States the power—silently no less—to disqualify a candidate for federal office.” But by excluding a federal candidate from the ballot based on section 3 a State does not exercise its own power to “disqualify” that candidate; it simply enforces a disqualification already imposed by the federal Constitution.

The Court makes much of the fact that States almost never[2]Only once, according to the Court. enforced section 3 against federal candidates (as opposed to State candidates) in the early years following ratification of the Fourteenth Amendment. However, the absence of State enforcement likely stemmed from a lack of enthusiasm for this task rather than a perceived lack of authority. (All but one former Confederate State initially refused to ratify the Fourteenth Amendment.) Indeed, congressional enactment of legislation mandating enforcement of section 3 was apparently based on dissatisfaction with State enforcement efforts.  

Finally, as the concurring opinion of Justices Sotomayor et al. points out, the five Justices who concluded that section 3 cannot be enforced even federally without additional congressional legislation offered “next to no support” for this conclusion.

In sum, the Court’s legal conclusions run counter to the Constitution’s text, structure, and logic and are thoroughly unpersuasive. However, there is a more straightforward and legally defensible (“originalist” even) rationale to support the decision’s outcome: The case that Trump “engaged in insurrection” is too weak to trigger disqualification under section 3.

There is widespread agreement that the January 6 attack on the Capitol was disgraceful and Trump’s conduct was despicable. However, whether this rose to the level of an “insurrection” for purposes of section 3 and if so whether Trump “engaged” in it pose difficult legal questions.

Legal definitions of “insurrection” at the time section 3 was enacted and now are arguably broad enough to be made to fit the events of January 6. Baude and Paulsen describe the term “insurrection” as “capacious” and define it as “concerted, forcible resistance to the authority of government to execute the laws in at least some significant respect.”[3]See page 676 of their previously linked article. However, if insurrection under section 3 sweeps this broadly it would encompass a host of actions that impede governmental functions in some way, such as garden-variety protests that often feature some violence and law-breaking. Baude and Paulsen assure that their definition “requires something more than a mere spontaneous, disorganized ‘riot’” but offer no clear criteria to draw the line.

A very broad interpretation of “engaging in” or inciting insurrection would also implicate free speech rights in many contexts. Moreover, as this case illustrates, the consequences of invoking section 3 are severe, anti-democratic, and potentially very disruptive to our political system. Notably, Congress removed section 3’s disability from all Confederates not long after its enactment.  

The foregoing considerations argue for a more circumspect approach that would construe these terms, at least as used in section 3, with a view toward section 3’s original purpose and context. Section 3 was enacted with a singular focus on the Civil War and Confederates who sought the dissolution of the United States by force of arms. Invoking it should be limited to actions bearing some significant resemblance to this in kind if not in magnitude—e.g., a concerted, violent undertaking that constitutes an attack on the United States itself.

Reprehensible as it was, the January 6 debacle hardly fits this description. It was a raucous, disorderly, loosely (if at all) organized protest that degenerated, apparently largely spontaneously, into a riot in which some (but not most) participants engaged in violence. However, it did not approach, either by design (if indeed it had any) or execution, a serious effort to overthrow the government.[4]See here and here for more background. On the contrary, it more closely resembled the kind of “spontaneous, disorganized riot” that Baude and Paulsen say falls outside the scope of section 3.

Likewise, treating Trump’s words and actions (reckless as they were) as engaging in or inciting insurrection is a stretch under contemporary First Amendment case law. Doing so could have chilling effects in many other contexts. It’s surely relevant in this regard that federal prosecutors who have been extremely aggressive in pursuing January 6 criminal cases declined to charge Trump or any participant in the January 6 attack with the federal crime of “insurrection” (18 U.S.C. 8323).

The many potentially far-reaching negative consequences and practical complications that section 3 poses, as acknowledged by the Court and discussed previously, further support setting a high bar for its application.

Nevertheless, the Court was clearly determined to avoid the insurrection issues at all cost–probably for understandable if intellectually suspect reasons. For one thing, the issues are messy factually and legally. For another, the Colorado courts developed a substantial record on these issues and it would have been awkward for the Court to summarily reverse them on it.

Perhaps most significant if speculating about the Justices’ motives, the issues of whether January 6 constituted an “insurrection” that Trump “engaged in” are as politically polarizing as they are legally fraught. No doubt the Court would have faced much more internal and external controversy by biting the bullet and addressing these issues than by retreating to the facile approach it adopted. Indeed, a decision based on the insurrection issues probably would have fractured the Court and subjected it to major criticism however it came out.

In the final analysis, one pundit observed of Trump v. Anderson:

“The Republic will not fall because the Court engaged in an unprincipled, pragmatic resolution where its self-interest was severely implicated.  But let’s not kid ourselves that this was originalism.  It was not.”

Fair enough, but there are two downsides. One is that the Court apparently gutted enforcement of section 3 in response to any future event that might bear a closer resemblance to the type of insurrection that prompted its enactment. Hopefully, the chances of such an event are exceptionally remote but who can be confident of that given the depths to which our politics and public discourse have fallen.

The other, more practical downside is that the Court leaves dangling the polarizing question of whether Trump is indeed an oath-breaking insurrectionist who should be constitutionally ineligible for the presidency even if there is no clear means to disqualify him. If Trump wins the election, this question is sure to hang over him and further erode our politics.

Footnotes

Footnotes
1 The Court specifically held that States could enforce section 3 against their own officials.
2 Only once, according to the Court.
3 See page 676 of their previously linked article.
4 See here and here for more background.

SCOTUS Should Pass on the Trump Immunity Case

Yesterday, a D.C. Circuit Court panel issued a 57-page unanimous decision rejecting Donald Trump’s claims of presidential immunity from criminal prosecution for his actions in trying to overturn the 2020 election. The panel’s comprehensive and detailed decision systematically rejected each of Trump’s arguments, which ranged from dubious to borderline frivolous.

In his effort to delay his criminal prosecution(s) for as long as possible, Trump will undoubtedly appeal. He could either first seek review by the full D.C. Circuit—a step the panel discouraged—or go directly to the Supreme Court. Either way, the case will surely land at the Supreme Court eventually. When it does, the Court should decline to hear it.

The last thing the Supreme Court needs is another politically charged Trump case—and another that would have to be decided on an expedited basis. It already has two Trump-related cases and may get more in addition to this one. Most notably, it will hear argument tomorrow on the case seeking to disqualify Trump from the 2024 presidential ballot under section 3 of the 14th Amendment. This is a more challenging case legally, and one the Court had no real choice but to accept given the already many and varied administrative and judicial decisions on the issue.

While Trump has a strong political interest in dragging out his criminal cases as long as he can, there is an obvious countervailing public interest in resolving them as soon as possible—ideally months before the 2024 election. However, there is a more basic reason the Supreme Court should decline the immunity case: there is simply no need for the Court to take it up under its usual criteria for review.

The Trump immunity case is, of course, highly politically significant. It also raises issues that are certainly interesting legally and largely unprecedented. (Fortunately, Trump is our first president to have engaged in conduct sufficiently egregious to trigger four separate criminal indictments.) However, the Supreme Court does not exist to weigh in on every publicly important federal legal issue. Rather, its role is to provide consistency and finality in federal statutory and constitutional law when its intervention is needed. Its consistent practice is to be highly selective in the cases it accepts for review.

There is no such compelling need here. The D.C. Circuit’s decision does not conflict with other decisions, as does the Trump disqualification case. Also, the bottom-line outcome of the decision appears clearly correct in its specific context. There may be serious issues regarding presidential immunity from prosecution in some future contexts, but this hardly seems true of Trump’s conduct at issue here. Thus, this case would not be a good vehicle for addressing more nuanced and challenging aspects of the broader subject.

Moreover, the Supreme Court does not set a precedent or endorse a lower court decision or its reasoning by declining to review it. If it denied review here, the Court would remain free to consider presidential immunity issues in a future case in the unfortunate event one arises. Alternatively, it could revisit the issue in this or another Trump case if one resulted in conviction and subsequent appeal based on a more developed record.

The Court wisely rejected Special Counsel Jack Smith’s invitation to decide the Trump immunity case by leapfrogging the D.C. Circuit. It should now likewise reject Trump’s appeal from that decision.

 

Trump Should Not Be Disqualified

It didn’t take long for the issue of whether section 3 of the Fourteenth Amendment disqualifies Donald Trump from the presidency to evolve from a “parlor game for law professors,” as one pundit put it, into all-out lawfareNumerous lawsuits have been filed to keep Trump off the 2024 ballot in various states. This effort received a major boost with the Colorado Supreme Court’s 4-3 decision that section 3 does indeed disqualify Trump.

Trump is manifestly unfit to be president and returning him to the White House could pose serious threats to our democracy. Thus, disqualifying him may seem appealing. However, it is not the way to go for legal and other reasons. Trump’s fate should be decided by the electorate, not the courts.

The legal case for disqualification is problematic.

Disqualifying Trump under section 3 entails resurrecting a constitutional provision that has lain largely dormant for over a century and extending it far beyond its original context.[1]See here for background. In the process, it requires answering yes to all the following subordinate legal and factual issues, each of which is unprecedented (with one exception), ambiguous, and seriously contested:

    • Is the presidency an “office” subject to section 3? It may seem obvious that it is, but some experts argue that it is not for technical reasons. Notably, the lower court in the Colorado case adopted this argument.
    • Is section 3 “self-executing,” so that a candidate can be disqualified “automatically” without additional congressional action or a prior adjudication affording due process? This is the one issue on which there is a precedent; it holds that section 3 is not self-executing.
    • Did the January 6, 2021, attack on the U.S. Capitol rise to the level of an “insurrection or rebellion” within the meaning of section 3?
    • If so, did Trump “engage” in it or give “aid or comfort” to “enemies” of the United States?

Issues three and four are the most equivocal, factually and legally. The Colorado courts relied heavily on the work of the House Select Committee to conclude that the January 6 attack was an “insurrection” within the scope of section 3. However, the Committee’s characterization involves considerable political spin. From a more objective perspective, it’s at least as plausible to view the chilling events of that day as a chaotic protest by an unruly mob that devolved into a riot but fell well short of an insurrection.

While there were some truly bad actors among the January 6 participants, the great majority were unarmed and unorganized. Most roamed the Capitol aimlessly, looking and acting more like jackasses than insurrectionists. They were able to breach the Capitol and delay the election certification not because of any concerted effort on their part but due to appalling law enforcement breakdowns.[2]These law enforcement failures never received the scrutiny and accountability they deserved. The House Select Committee was specifically charged with investigating them but essentially ignored that … Continue reading Tellingly, not one of the January 6 participants was charged with the federal crime of “rebellion or insurrection.” This despite the fact that federal prosecutors, judges, and juries in the District of Columbia threw the book at them in every way they could.

Even if January 6 were to be regarded as an insurrection, it’s far from clear legally or factually that Trump “engaged” in it. He did not participate in or plot an attack on the Capitol. (Indeed, there’s no evidence of any coherent plot.) It’s questionable whether his exhortations crossed the line from recklessness to incitement of violence under applicable case law. Here again, the approach of prosecutors is telling. Special Counsel Jack Smith has been very aggressive in pursuing Trump but declined to charge him with insurrection or any insurrection-related crime.

One additional fact has been largely ignored but seems highly relevant: Congress is on record acquitting Trump of the charge of “incitement of insurrection” in his second impeachment trial.

Legal and prudential considerations support a narrow reading of section 3.

Disqualification proponents construe the term “insurrection” sweepingly, and the January 6 attack can be made to fit some legal definitions. However, several factors support a narrower definition for purposes of section 3 that sets a high bar for disqualification. Section 3 was enacted with a very specific purpose and meaning in mind. The “insurrection or rebellion” it referenced was the Civil War and those disqualified were Confederates who sought to destroy the United States. Given this original context, it seems reasonable to limit section 3 to actions at least roughly comparable in kind or intent if not magnitude. While January 6 was a disgrace, it doesn’t begin to compare.

Furthermore, section 3 is highly undemocratic. Many have expressed qualms about depriving voters of electoral choices, particularly the shock to our political system that would result from eliminating a candidate as prominent as Trump. The Washington Post editorialized:

“[A]cross multiple aspects of the case and on the insurrection question especially, the law is unclear. In the absence of clarity, a body of unelected officials should be reluctant to prevent the country’s citizens from choosing an elected official to lead them.”

The political shockwaves from disqualifying Trump actually go far beyond him. Section 3 potentially reaches a host of candidates for federal and state office as well as incumbent officials. Injecting a sweeping approach to section 3 into our already polarized politics would breed many lawsuits against many politicians, making our politics even more toxic and chaotic for years to come.

Two final observations:

The Supreme Court will face more heat.

The Colorado decision makes it virtually inevitable that the Supreme Court will have to decide the disqualification issue, probably on an expedited basis. It now has two other Trump-related cases that could affect the 2024 election and it may get more.[3]See here for background. The Court is already subject to relentless (albeit spurious) attacks on its integrity and “legitimacy” from leftists who dislike its perceived turn to the right. Trump also enthusiastically plays the game of demonizing the courts when they displease him. Thus, the Court will surely face more demagoguery however it decides the Trump-related cases. It can at least minimize this by reaching consensus decisions that cut across ideological lines. Hopefully, the justices will work hard to do so.

Proponents of disqualifying Trump should be careful what they wish for.

One irony in all of this may help explain why the reaction to the Colorado decision from the left has been guarded or even negative:  Chances are that removing Trump from the 2024 presidential ballot would result in the election of his Republican replacement. Trump probably is the weakest general election candidate against President Biden, particularly if he is convicted of a crime. (His lead over Biden in early polling likely signifies only that many consider him the lesser of two evils.) Given his massive personal baggage, Trump’s favorability is confined mainly to his ardent base. If he is disqualified, whoever Republicans pick to replace him should have broader appeal to the general electorate. If the courts strike Trump from the ballot, his apoplectic core supporters would presumably rally behind that nominee out of intense anger and desire for vengeance if nothing else.

 

Footnotes

Footnotes
1 See here for background.
2 These law enforcement failures never received the scrutiny and accountability they deserved. The House Select Committee was specifically charged with investigating them but essentially ignored that part of its mandate.
3 See here for background.

If Trump Wins

The increasingly realistic prospect of Donald Trump back in the White House has caused widespread alarm. New York Times writers foresee an authoritarian assault on our democracy that its institutional guardrails might be unable to contain. The Atlantic devoted an entire issue to this possibility. A prominent neocon joined in, warning of a potential Trump “dictatorship.” Others believe such concerns are nonsense or at least greatly  exaggerated. However, many factors, some systemic and some specific to Trump, suggest that a second Trump term could indeed pose an unprecedented threat to our democracy. Consider:

The current state of our democracy is fragile and potentially vulnerable to an autocrat.

The distribution of power in our constitutional system has evolved in ways quite different from what the framers envisioned. Their original concept was that most government authority over the citizenry would continue to reside in and be diffused among the states, with the federal government confined to those powers expressly assigned it by the Constitution. Over time this balance of power has reversed; the federal government now exercises by far the greatest influence over the lives of American citizens.

The allocation of power within the federal government has also shifted dramatically. Congress, originally designed as the primary policymaking branch of the federal government, has abdicated much of its authority to the president and the vast executive branch bureaucracies he controls. Congress struggles to perform even its remaining core constitutional responsibilities. In practice, therefore, the president now holds most federal policymaking authority.

On top of this, our politics are broken. An effective democracy depends upon good faith, constructive interaction between political factions that share a common set of fundamental goals and beliefs although they compete over how best to effectuate them. Today’s politics are dominated by increasingly extreme, polarized factions whose only commonality is mutual contempt and whose agendas are at odds with the more moderate views of most Americans. The results:

The public itself bears much responsibility for this state of affairs. In a democracy, the citizens get the government they deserve. As Benjamin Franklin famously observed, the founders delivered to the people of the United States “a republic if you can keep it.” However, much of the public lacks interest in keeping it, instead tuning out of our democratic processes. Only about 60 to 67 percent of eligible voters voted in recent presidential elections, about 40 percent in mid-term general elections, and about 20 percent in primaries.

Trump clearly fits the mold of an autocrat.

By any objective standard, Trump is unfit to be president. He defied presidential and democratic norms throughout his chaotic first term. He became even more outrageous in the wake of his 2020 election loss, engaging in conduct that was clearly impeachable and perhaps criminal.

Even beyond his fraudulent efforts to overturn the election, Trump’s words and actions consistently demonstrate contempt for the rule of law and the core institutions of our democracy. His rhetoric is becoming ever more extreme and unhinged. Some of this may be hyperbole given his status as a world-class liar and con artist. However, to paraphrase Maya Angelou, when someone repeatedly shows you who they are by word and deed, believe them.

It’s hard to tell exactly what Trump would do in a second term. He is not a militarist or ultranationalist bent on world conquest. Indeed, he’s more of an isolationist who would embolden rather than challenge our foreign rivals. What is clear is that Trump’s only real interest is self-indulgence. Terminating the various federal prosecutions against him would surely be his first priority. He also seems intent on pursuing “vengeance” against his many perceived enemies, whatever that might entail. Beyond this, who knows?

Whatever Trump attempts, he would have plenty of enablers and few constraints in a second term.

Despite his glaring flaws, Trump remains the odds-on favorite among GOP voters. Hardly any Republican leaders and influencers, including his primary opponents, are willing to confront him; shamefully, most still embrace him. Evidently, they are fine with electing a president who scorns our democracy.

If Trump wins in November, these folks will most likely control both houses of Congress. The Senate math already strongly favors a Republican takeover of that body, and a Trump victory probably would boost enough Republicans to maintain or increase their House majority. Few if any Congressional Republicans have the courage or integrity to buck Trump. Thus, the legislative branch would be wholly subservient to him.

Nor would Trump face pushback from within his administration. Many distinguished Republicans and others served in Trump’s first term (often at great cost to their reputations) and provided some check on his worst impulses. His executive branch appointees a second time around would probably consist overwhelmingly of Trump sycophants all too willing to do his bidding without question.

Only the federal courts will stand in Trump’s way.

The one significant guardrail against Trump’s excesses would be the federal judiciary. Thus far, the courts have held up well against Trump. Federal judges and justices, including many appointed by Trump, ruled against some of his worst policies and uniformly rejected his bogus efforts to overturn the 2020 election. There is no objective reason to doubt that they would continue to do their jobs with integrity.

Unfortunately, there may be reason to doubt whether Trump would comply with their decisions. Over recent decades, both political parties have damaged public confidence in the courts and threatened their effectiveness by politicizing the judicial appointments process. Many on the left, displeased with the Supreme Court’s decisions, continue to level baseless attacks on the Court’s legitimacy. Such efforts to undermine the credibility of the courts may come back to bite them if Trump wins. He enthusiastically plays the same game of demonizing the courts when they displease him. He might well defy them during a second term if he thinks he could get away with it.

Critics would be wise to reconsider their relentless attacks on the federal judiciary. In the awful event that Trump returns to the White House, the judiciary will be our primary, and perhaps only, defense against him.

Is Trump Ineligible to Run for President?

Just when it seemed the 2024 presidential election couldn’t get more combustible, with Donald Trump facing four criminal indictments containing 91 felony counts, two law professors fan the flames. In a forthcoming law review article, William Baude and Michael Stokes Paulsen argue that Trump is disqualified from being President by a heretofore obscure constitutional provision.

They cite section 3 of the Fourteenth Amendment, which disqualifies from federal or state office individuals who previously took an oath to support the Constitution of the United States as government officials and then “engaged in insurrection or rebellion against the same, or [gave] aid or comfort to the enemies thereof.” They maintain that Trump’s efforts to overturn the 2020 election clearly fall within section 3; therefore, “every official, state or federal, who judges qualifications” has not only the authority but the obligation to keep him off the 2024 ballot.

Needless to say, the professors’ theory is attracting lots of attention both pro[1]See here, here, and here. and con.[2]See here, here, here, and here. One argument gaining ground among the “cons” is that the presidency is not an “office” subject to section 3 disqualification. No doubt many Trump opponents will be eager to give it a try.[3]Indeed, it is already attracting increasing interest on the left. However, invoking section 3 against Trump would add more chaos to our already chaotic and polarized politics and the case for doing so is far less clear-cut than the professors let on.

By way of background, section 3 was enacted to penalize former government officials who served the Confederacy during the Civil War in violation of their previously sworn allegiance to the United States. Section 3 includes language giving Congress the option to remove its disqualification. Congress did just that in two late Nineteenth Century statutes by freeing all Civil War era individuals from disqualification. This effectively nullified section 3 in relation to its original purpose, and it has lain largely dormant until now.

However, section 3 is still part of the Constitution and its text is not explicitly confined to its original purpose. Thus, the professors are surely correct that section 3 remains legally operative. They are also probably correct (although less obviously) that an individual can be subject to disqualification under section 3 without having previously been adjudged an insurrectionist or revolutionary as, for example, by conviction in an impeachment or criminal proceeding.[4]In making this point, the professors rather confusingly describe section 3 as “self-executing.” Of course, no law is literally self-executing; laws cannot enforce themselves. An individual would … Continue reading

Their conclusions regarding the scope and application of the reincarnated section 3 are more problematic. They insist that the case for disqualifying Trump under it is “not even close.” But this is because they resolve virtually all relevant legal and factual ambiguities in favor of interpreting section 3 “sweepingly,” both in general and as applied to Trump. Without attempting to address everything in their 126-page article, the following are some major sticking points.

First, while section 3 is not a dead letter and must be presumed to mean something today, why give it the “capacious” scope that the professors do? Section 3 was enacted with a very specific and relatively narrow purpose in mind. Its original public meaning is clear:“insurrection or revolution” referred to the Civil War, and those disqualified for “engag[ing]” in it or giving “aid or comfort” to “enemies” were servants of the Confederacy—a regime that sought the forcible dissolution of the United States.

Although no longer operative, section 3’s original purpose and meaning should be relevant to assessing its current application. Thus, it seems  reasonable to construe section 3 as limited to contexts at least roughly equivalent to them, i.e., involving some kind of existential threat to the United States itself. Contrary to this, the professors give section 3 the broadest scope its language can bear, extending it far beyond anything resembling its original context.

There are additional reasons for giving section 3 a much narrower scope. The professors’ sweeping approach creates many potential slippery slopes between “insurrection or rebellion,” on the one hand, and protests or even riots that may be violent and disrupt government functions but still, as they recognize, fall outside of section 3.[5]See footnote 407 on page 113 of their article. Their approach also creates potential conflict between section 3 and other constitutional provisions, such as those guaranteeing freedom of speech and due process of law (see below).[6]They acknowledge these issues but give them short shrift. See pages 49-61. For example, they argue that section 3 takes precedence over constitutional provisions enacted earlier in time in case of … Continue reading

Equating section 3 to the application of routine candidate eligibility rules, as the professors do, is highly dubious. In marked contrast to section 3, such qualification requirements (e.g., age, citizenship, residency) are non-punitive and usually self-evident. Prospective candidates naturally assume the burden of meeting them; those who can’t simply have no right to run for office. By contrast, section 3 deprives otherwise qualified candidates of their right to run for office. Under the professors’ theory, election clerks could simply refuse to list a supposed section 3 violator on the ballot without any prior due process, thereby forcing the individual to assume the burden of proving their non-disqualification.[7]Application of section 3 to candidates for election would depend mainly on state law. As a practical matter, resorting to the varied state processes could prove more challenging than one might think.

Another reason to construe section 3 narrowly and permit its use only sparingly is its fundamentally undemocratic effect. By keeping candidates for election off the ballot, it denies voters the opportunity to make their own judgments about the qualifications and fitness of those candidates.

Finally, sweeping application of section 3 is a recipe for more dissonance in our already discordant politics. In the near term, it encourages a host of lawsuits over Trump’s eligibility, probably lasting well into the 2024 election cycle and creating further uncertainty and instability. But that’s just for starters. While the current focus is on Trump, section 3 extends far beyond him—reaching all candidates for federal and state office, as well as incumbents of those offices, who have taken the federal constitutional oath. Injecting the professors’ expansive reading into our increasingly toxic politics will likely spawn attempts to weaponize section 3 in many different ways against many candidates and incumbent officials.

Turning to the application of section 3 to Trump, the professors base their case on “the overall package of events” following the 2020 election.[8]See generally pages 111-121. Here again, they consistently resolve ambiguities, including many over interpretation of the facts, in favor of section 3’s applicability.

They maintain that the January 6 attack on the U.S. Capitol clearly constituted an “insurrection” within the meaning of section 3. But there is considerable debate featuring much political spin over how to characterize this disgraceful event. Another at least equally plausible interpretation is that an unruly protest careened out of control and turned into a riot, but one falling well short of an “insurrection.”

In this regard, the January 6 mob was largely unorganized and unarmed. Although some were violent, most participants who entered the Capitol wandered about aimlessly–taking selfies, committing minor acts of theft and vandalism, and acting more like jackasses than insurrectionists. The breach of the Capitol and disruption of the election certification were attributable less to any grand strategy or concerted effort on their part than to the incompetence and leadership failures of law-enforcement agencies, for which they have yet to be fully accountable.

The prosecutions of January 6 participants are also telling. Federal prosecutors have come down very hard on January 6 defendants. Yet fewer than 10 percent of the over 1,100 participants who have been indicted face charges involving weapons or acts of violence. Fewer than 5 percent face conspiracy-related charges, mainly seditious conspiracy under 18 U.S.C. 2384. Not a single participant has been charged with the specific federal crime of “rebellion or insurrection” (18 U.S.C. 2383).[9]Seditious conspiracy under 18 U.S.C. 2384 overlaps insurrection in some respects. Section 2384 prohibits, in part, conspiracies “to overthrow, put down, or to destroy by force the Government of the … Continue reading Indeed, the Justice Department document describing the various charges nowhere refers to January 6 as an insurrection or rebellion.

Even if one still insists that the January 6 attack on the Capitol was an insurrection under section 3, it’s far from clear that Trump “engaged” in it.[10]Of course, Trump’s reprehensible behavior regarding the January 6 events was clearly impeachable on other grounds. He did not participate directly, and his remarks in advance of it seem too ambiguous to constitute incitement. The professors concede that much of Trump’s “rambling” speech to the protesters was “innuendo.”[11]Page 119. Significantly,  Congress specifically acquitted Trump of “incitement of insurrection” in his second impeachment.[12]The professors emphasize that a majority in each House of Congress agreed with this charge. But this is as irrelevant as the fact that a candidate who lost the presidency in the Electoral College won … Continue reading Moreover, Federal Special Counsel Jack Smith declined to charge Trump with insurrection or rebellion, seditious conspiracy, or any other potentially insurrection-related crime.

The professors further stretch in suggesting that Trump gave aid or comfort to “enemies.” This concept, closely akin to treason, usually connotes assisting enemies of the United States during a declared war. Still another stretch is including in their “overall package” Trump’s many efforts apart from January 6 to overturn the election by pressuring election officials to “find” votes, organizing fake electors, etc. While these actions may well be fraudulent and criminal in other ways, they lack the element of violence that an “insurrection or rebellion” generally features.

*                  *                  *                  *                  *

Trump is manifestly unfit for the presidency. However, conjuring up section 3 to disqualify him rests on a shaky legal foundation and would add considerably more devisiveness and instability to our already fragile politics. It would be better to adopt a limited interpretation of section 3 that reserves it for extreme situations bearing at least a passing resemblance to its original context. Presumably, such situations would arise very rarely if ever.

Nevertheless, it’s all but inevitable that someone (probably many) will employ this tactic in the coming months. When that happens, one can only hope that the issue reaches the Supreme Court quickly for definitive resolution.

 

 

 

 

Footnotes

Footnotes
1 See here, here, and here.
2 See here, here, here, and here. One argument gaining ground among the “cons” is that the presidency is not an “office” subject to section 3 disqualification.
3 Indeed, it is already attracting increasing interest on the left.
4 In making this point, the professors rather confusingly describe section 3 as “self-executing.” Of course, no law is literally self-executing; laws cannot enforce themselves. An individual would not actually be disqualified by section 3 unless and until an appropriate administrative or judicial authority determined that section 3 did indeed apply to the individual. See footnote 7 in this regard.
5 See footnote 407 on page 113 of their article.
6 They acknowledge these issues but give them short shrift. See pages 49-61. For example, they argue that section 3 takes precedence over constitutional provisions enacted earlier in time in case of conflict. But this is the last resort in interpreting potentially conflicting legal texts. The favored approach is finding a way to reconcile them.
7 Application of section 3 to candidates for election would depend mainly on state law. As a practical matter, resorting to the varied state processes could prove more challenging than one might think.
8 See generally pages 111-121.
9 Seditious conspiracy under 18 U.S.C. 2384 overlaps insurrection in some respects. Section 2384 prohibits, in part, conspiracies “to overthrow, put down, or to destroy by force the Government of the United States, or to levy war against them, or to oppose by force the authority thereof, or by force to prevent, hinder, or delay the execution of any law of the United States.” Notably, the January 6 conspiracy defendants were not charged with the insurrection-related portions of section 2384—i.e., overthrowing or making war against the United States. Rather, they were charged only with conspiracy to prevent, etc., the execution of a federal law—i.e., congressional certification of the 2020 election results. See ¶¶ 15-16 of the indictment.
10 Of course, Trump’s reprehensible behavior regarding the January 6 events was clearly impeachable on other grounds.
11 Page 119.
12 The professors emphasize that a majority in each House of Congress agreed with this charge. But this is as irrelevant as the fact that a candidate who lost the presidency in the Electoral College won a majority of the popular vote.

The Third Trump Indictment: Controversial But Essential

The indictment is solid legally and factually. Criticisms of it based on its substance and other considerations are unpersuasive. Disregarding this case would be far more problematic than pursuing it.

Donald Trump now faces three criminal indictments and counting. [1]A Georgia grand jury may issue a fourth indictment for election interference, and the current indictments could be expanded. The first indictment, by the Manhattan District Attorney regarding hush money payments to Stormy Daniels, is by far the weakest. It was widely panned as politically motivated and legally dubious. If this case goes to trial and Trump is convicted, the conviction would likely be overturned on appeal.

The second indictment, by Justice Department Special Counsel Jack Smith relating to improper possession and handling of classified documents at Mar-a-Lago and obstruction of federal efforts to recover them, is the strongest. There is a broad consensus among legal experts across the political spectrum that prosecutors have Trump dead to rights in this case. His best hope may be a hung jury, given the relatively Trump-friendly jury pool in the Florida district where the case will be tried.

The third and most recent indictment, also brought by Special Counsel Smith, presents the most serious and complex case. It goes to the heart of Trump’s efforts to overturn the 2020 presidential election result based on his pervasive, patently false “stolen election” claims. This case has also produced the most diverse reactions. Media and expert opinion on the left is generally supportive; much opinion on the right, although not all, is highly critical.

The Facts

The 45-page indictment was released on August 1.[2]The Lawfare website has an excellent overview of the indictment as well as detailed explanations of the facts and statutes it cites. The facts it alleges are familiar: Invoking knowingly false claims of election irregularities, Trump and his co-conspirators pressured state election officials to alter their vote counts, “find” votes for him, dismiss legitimate electors, and substitute fake pro-Trump electors. They organized the fake electors and had them submit false certificates in connection with the January 6 congressional election certification proceeding. They relentlessly pressured Vice President Pence to exceed his constitutional role and assume control over the election certification by rejecting legitimate electors in favor of Trump’s fake ones or at least delaying the certification. (¶ 10 of the indictment)

According to critics, it will be hard to disprove that Trump sincerely believed the election was “stolen” from him. They point out that the indictment contains no “smoking gun” evidence from Trump’s own mouth that he knew he lost.[3]Its absence from the indictment does not necessarily mean that such evidence does not exist. In fact, there are indications that Trump acknowledged his loss to some staffers, including White House … Continue reading However, this is a red herring argument; the case doesn’t turn on whether Trump somehow actually believed the election was stolen.[4]Of course, it’s highly implausible that Trump did (does) believe this given the total lack of supporting evidence, the mountain of contradictory evidence, and the fact that he has shown himself … Continue reading Rather, the key factual issue is whether the many false claims of specific election irregularities by Trump and his co-conspirators in support of their actions to overturn the election were knowing lies.

The indictment presents copious evidence that they were. Trump and the others asserted detailed factual claims they had no basis to believe were true and that they had been repeatedly and authoritatively told were false. (See generally ¶¶ 13-52) Moreover, the indictment cites instances in which Trump unquestionably knew he was lying. For example:

    • He asserted that Georgia election officials did not address a series of his false claims just one day after the officials refuted those claims in detail in a phone conversation with him. (¶ 32)
    • He told Pence that the Justice Department was finding major infractions regarding the election after they told him they were not. (¶ 90.b)
    • He approved a statement that he and Pence “are in total agreement that the Vice President has the power to act” despite Pence’s repeated denials to Trump that he had such authority. (¶ 99)
    • He asserted that some states wanted to re-certify their elector submissions when he knew they had no such intention. (¶ 104)

Finally, the indictment presents evidence that Trump knew he was engaged in a scheme of lies. After Justice Department officials refuted  his claims and declined to challenge the election, Trump responded: “Just say that the election was corrupt and leave the rest to me and the Republican congressmen.” (¶ 74) After Pence refused Trump’s demand that he assert broad authority over the election certification, Trump responded: “You’re too honest.” (¶ 90.c)

The Law

The indictment is noteworthy for the crimes it charges as well as those it omits. The included charges focus on the efforts of Trump and his co-conspirators to overturn the election and prevent its certification through various fraudulent schemes. It does not contain charges relating directly to the attack on the U.S. Capitol, such as insurrection and seditious conspiracy, as the House January 6 Committee had recommended.[5]See pp. 109-112 of the Committee’s Final Report. This reflects a measured approach that best matches the charges with the evidence. For the most part, the charges set forth in the indictment are straightforward in relation to the facts alleged.

The first count of the indictment charges a violation of 18 U.S.C. 371, which makes it a crime to “conspire . . . to defraud the United States, or any agency thereof in any manner or for any purpose.” As summarized above, the indictment alleges extensive fraudulent efforts by Trump et al. to undercut the legitimate outcome of the presidential election and defeat or delay congressional certification of it.

Some critics of the indictment contend that 18 U.S.C. 371 does not apply because fraud under federal criminal law is limited to schemes to swindle victims out of money or property. As discussed in the Justice Department’s prosecutorial manual, however, the courts have applied section 371 broadly, consistent with its sweeping language, and have held specifically that it is not limited to fraud aimed at money or property. Those arguing for a narrower reading rely on cases dealing with a different fraud statute (18 U.S.C. 1343) that, unlike section 371, does explicitly reference fraud to obtain money or property.

The second and third counts of the indictment charge violations of 18 U.S.C. 1512(c)(2) and 1512(k). Subsection 1512(c) provides:

“(c) Whoever corruptly—

     “(1) alters, destroys, mutilates, or conceals a record, document, or other object, or attempts to do so, with the intent to impair the object’s integrity or availability for use in an official proceeding; or

     “(2) otherwise obstructs, influences, or impedes any official proceeding, or attempts to do so,

shall be fined under this title or imprisoned not more than 20 years, or both.”

Subsection 1512(k) criminalizes conspiracies to violate subsection (c).

Section 1512(c)(2) has been successfully invoked to convict many of the rioters in the January 6 attack on the Capitol, and its use for that purpose has been affirmed by the U.S. Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit. This statue does not require acts of violence and seems clearly applicable to Trump and his co-conspirators as well.

One potential complication is that a January 6 rioter is seeking Supreme Court review of his conviction on the basis that section 1512(c)(2) only applies to evidence-tampering in connection with an official proceeding. He contends that that the word “otherwise” in paragraph (c)(2) means that a violation of that paragraph is limited to conduct within the general scope of paragraph (c)(1). If the Supreme Court were to adopt this more restrictive interpretation, it would jeopardize the convictions of many January 6 rioters. However, Trump could still be covered since his conduct involved tampering with documentation and other evidence relating to congressional certification of the election. In any event, the section 1512(c)(2) charge against Trump, like the 18 U.S.C. 371 charge, is clearly consistent with the law as it stands now.

The fourth and final count is a violation 18 U.S.C. 241, which prohibits conspiracies to injure, oppress, threaten, or intimidate anyone in the exercise of a right or privilege under the Constitution or laws of the United States. This count may be a stretch since section 241 typically applies to voter intimidation rather than actions relating to ballots already cast. On the other hand, the courts have applied section 241 more broadly.[6]See the Lawfare statutory summary cited in footnote 2 for more on this.

Other Considerations

Critics have raised objections that go beyond the specifics of the indictment, but they are tenuous at best.

Some argue that the prosecution violates Trump’s free speech rights under the First Amendment. However, Trump is not being prosecuted for insisting, no matter how implausibly, that the election was stolen from him or for the many lawful, if frivolous, judicial actions he pursued to contest the election. Rather, the prosecution is based on the alleged fraudulent schemes he and his co-conspirators instigated to overturn the election through extralegal means featuring extensive, knowingly false claims.

Critics also assert that the prosecution is politically motivated and an example of uneven justice compared, in particular, to the lenient treatment of Hunter Biden. They also make much of the timing of the indictment in relation to the 2024 presidential election. Of course, it would have been much better if this case (and the others involving Trump) could have been resolved prior to the election campaign. However, to the extent that the time taken involved anything more than the complexities of the case, it seems attributable to an abundance of caution on the part of Justice Department leaders in going after Trump.

In any event and most significantly, there is no hint of political motivation or bad faith on Special Counsel Smith’s part. As detailed above, his indictment is measured and well supported by the facts and statutes cited. The same is true of his indictment in the classified documents case, which even many of the critics here supported. The attacks on the good faith of this prosecution call to mind liberal assaults on the legitimacy of the Supreme Court, which conservatives rightly decry. Both illustrate the degradation of our public discourse in which partisans on each side are quick to attack the integrity of government officials and institutions when they disagree with their decisions.

Finally, some critics maintain that the prosecution of a former president for conduct while in office, particularly one running again, is a grave and potentially divisive undertaking that should be attempted, if at all, only when the case is airtight. One critic prone to hyperbole went so far as to compare the indictment to the action of a “banana republic.”

It’s certainly true that prosecuting a former president is a very serious matter, but so is the conduct Trump is accused of. His reprehensible actions following the election clearly violated his constitutional responsibilities and demonstrated utter contempt for the most basic democratic norms. If anything equates to “banana republic” conduct, his surely did. Even critics of the indictment (other than MAGA zealots and craven Republican politicians) acknowledge the outrageousness of Trump’s post-election conduct.[7]See, e.g., here and here.

It’s by now clear as day that Trump committed impeachable acts  warranting his removal from office and disqualification from future office. However, the timing did not permit full development of the impeachment case against him, and the House overreached by charging him with “incitement of insurrection.” Also, it was questionable whether Trump could be convicted after leaving office.

The case laid out against Trump in the indictment is not a slam-dunk; no case this complex could be. However, it is well grounded in the facts and the law. Declining to pursue it and failing once again to hold Trump accountable would be far more divisive and harmful for the Nation than allowing it to play out.

Footnotes

Footnotes
1 A Georgia grand jury may issue a fourth indictment for election interference, and the current indictments could be expanded.
2 The Lawfare website has an excellent overview of the indictment as well as detailed explanations of the facts and statutes it cites.
3 Its absence from the indictment does not necessarily mean that such evidence does not exist. In fact, there are indications that Trump acknowledged his loss to some staffers, including White House Chief of Staff Mark Meadows. See here and here.
4 Of course, it’s highly implausible that Trump did (does) believe this given the total lack of supporting evidence, the mountain of contradictory evidence, and the fact that he has shown himself to be a serial liar. If he was (is) this delusional, it would cast serious doubt on his mental fitness.
5 See pp. 109-112 of the Committee’s Final Report.
6 See the Lawfare statutory summary cited in footnote 2 for more on this.
7 See, e.g., here and here.

Can No Labels Move the Major Parties Closer to the People?

As America gears up for the 2024 presidential election, the political landscape is bleak:

    • Public support for both Democrats and Republicans in our two-party duopoly has declined steadily over the past two decades. Almost twice as many Americans (49%) identify as independents than with either major party (25% each).
    • The leading candidates for each party’s presidential nomination are extremely unpopular; the public dreads a Biden-Trump rematch in 2024. Most prominent leaders in both parties also have negative favorability ratings.
    • Neither party has a policy agenda that aligns with majority public opinion. The Republican Party has degenerated into little more than the cult of Trump with no discernible agenda other than subservience to him. The Democratic Party’s agenda, increasingly set by its far left, embraces the divisive politics of identity, victimization, and tribalism. This turns off most voters, including many of its own party members.
    •  Civility has virtually disappeared from our civil discourse. The activists who dominate both parties drive our politics toward polarization and away from collaborative engagement to solve problems. While differing in their objectives, activists on both sides use similar methods. They suppress dissent and even good faith debate, seek to delegitimize individuals and institutions that don’t toe their line, and rarely let facts or reason get in the way of their ideologies and orthodoxies.
    • Congress, mired in gridlock and dysfunction, struggles to perform its most basic tasks and abdicates much of its constitutional authority to the executive branch and the courts.
    • One of the few things that unites the parties is fiscal irresponsibility. Both turn a blind eye to the huge fiscal challenges that pose an existential threat to future generations. They occasionally join forces to exacerbate them.
    • Unsurprisingly given the above, the vast majority of the public thinks the country is headed in the wrong direction. Americans have little confidence in the Nation’s governmental institutions or most other institutions, such as the media.
    • Our politicians and their media cheerleaders are seriously out of touch with a majority of the citizenry. Most Americans are not ideologically rigid; they are pragmatic and generally hold centrist or moderate political views. There is broad public agreement on numerous policy issues that stymie our ruling classes. Ordinary citizens much prefer constructive engagement and compromise over today’s polarization and extremism.
  • A group called No Labels is gearing up to enter this fraught arena, laying the foundation for a third-party campaign in 2024. They are considering running a bipartisan “unity ticket” of candidates for president and vice president (one Republican and one Democrat), and they have published a centrist “common sense” policy agenda. A recent poll shows about 20 percent support for a No Labels ticket even before its candidates are named.

One might think the potential of formidable competition like this would prompt the duopolists to take a hard look at their 2024 offerings. However, the two major parties show no sign of humility or introspection. A headline from a New York Times op-ed succinctly captures their message to the voters: “Repulsed by Biden vs. Trump? Tough.”

The conventional wisdom, apparently shared by both parties, is that Democrats have more to lose from a No Labels candidacy. Therefore, while the Republican response has been somewhat muted, panicked Democrats are in full attack mode. They even sued in one swing state to keep No Labels off the ballot. In typical fashion, their media allies strain to discredit No Labels as a dark money,  closet Trump-supporting, Republican front group. This is nonsense. No Labels has promoted bipartisanship throughout its existence of well over a decade. Its leadership includes many prominent individuals—Democrats, Republicans, and independents—with long and distinguished records of public service and a clear commitment to good government.

Attacks disparaging the No Labels policy agenda as vague and anodyne (e.g., here and here) also miss the mark. Unlike the major parties, No Labels does not stake out one-sided positions that it claims are unquestionably the only “right” answers to complex problems. Rather, its common sense platform advocates core criteria that provide a framework for debate and compromise to arrive at specific solutions that can achieve broad, bipartisan support.

The critics do raise one legitimate concern. While No Labels may be the best choice for many voters, it’s very hard to see a realistic path to electoral college victory for it given today’s entrenched, fractured politics. At this point, it seems more likely to play a spoiler role and, if the conventional wisdom is correct,[1]Of course, the conventional could be wrong. perhaps tip the election to Trump. Unappealing as a second Biden term may be, returning Trump to the White House would be far worse.

However, this is no reason for No Labels to stand down now. There are months to go before the presidential race fully takes shape and a lot can happen in the interim. Moreover, the No Labels leadership is quite clear that they have no interest in being a spoiler. They will drop out if they see no reasonable chance to win the presidency as circumstances unfold. They will also pull out if one or the other major party nominates a candidate more acceptable to the public than Biden and Trump.

Indeed, there is every reason for No Labels to stay in the race over the coming months in order to keep pressure on the major parties to shift back toward the mainstream. Clearly, this is No Labels’ overriding goal. Whether it can achieve it remains to be seen but the effort is surely worthwhile. If either major party does nominate a less flawed candidate and adopts a policy agenda more in tune with American public sentiment, it will be a real victory for No Labels and for the American people. It will also greatly improve that party’s chance of winning the presidency in 2024.

Footnotes

Footnotes
1 Of course, the conventional could be wrong.